https://chatgpt.com/c/67ca53ac-01b4-8012-b4e5-1c2c17efb605

Cannot be shared.



Why do we find the behavior of corrupt politicians rather absurd?

Reasoned about corrupt politician behavior for 8 seconds

Understanding absurdity

OK, let me see. Exploring why corrupt politicians' actions seem absurd, I aim for a philosophical perspective with general references for verification.

Analyzing contradictions

I'm exploring the absurdity of corrupt politicians through moral frameworks like Plato and Aristotle, Machiavelli's "The Prince," and existential philosophy, particularly Camus's concept of the Absurd.

Examining comedic paradoxes

I'm mapping out the absurdity of corrupt politicians by analyzing comedic and tragic-comedic elements, ethical tensions, and references to philosophical ideas like the social contract and moral condemnation.

In ordinary language, calling a politician “corrupt” already implies a betrayal of what politics is meant to uphold: the public trust, the common good, or the shared rules of social life. We frequently find that corrupt politicians’ behavior strikes us as absurd because of the mismatch between (1) the role they inhabit—which is supposed to represent integrity and public service—and (2) their self-serving actions. In philosophy, this mismatch is often described in terms of “the absurd” as a conflict between what we logically or ethically expect and what actually transpires.

Below are several angles that help clarify why corrupt politicians seem so absurd:

  1. Expectations versus Reality

  2. Conflict with Normative Ideals of Leadership

  3. The Absurdity of Incongruity

  4. Power, Cynicism, and the “Theater of Politics”

In short, the absurdity arises from the stark contradiction between the ethical ideals that society places on its leaders and the flagrant moral failures of actual corrupt politicians. We expect them to embody (or at least approximate) principles of justice and integrity, yet we see greed, deceit, and hypocrisy. Philosophically, this gap between “what should be” and “what is” often elicits reactions of disbelief, dark humor, or cynicism—the mark of the absurd.

Suggested readings for further verification and exploration:

These sources provide philosophical frameworks (from classical virtue ethics to modern existentialism) that illuminate why political corruption can seem so fundamentally at odds with the purpose of leadership and, ultimately, why we label it as “absurd.”

You said:

Why do voters have such high but unrealistic expectations for politicians when they are fully aware of what kinds of moral compromises are required to become successful politicians nowadays? Who are being absurd here?

Reasoned for 7 seconds

Analyzing voter expectations

Voters have high, unrealistic expectations for politicians, knowing the moral compromises involved. This involves examining moral hypocrisy, illusions, and the paradox of expected virtue versus required compromise.

Balancing illusions

Both politicians and voters engage in magical thinking to manage the tension between perceived promises and actual governance realities. This embrace of wishful thinking perpetuates the absurd conflict.

Our high moral expectations of politicians often stand in striking tension with the widespread knowledge that “dirty work” and moral compromises are often inherent in modern political life. This tension itself can appear absurd—not only in the philosophers’ sense of a dissonance between reality and ideals, but also in everyday talk of “political hypocrisy.” Below are several perspectives on why voters cling to these high expectations despite the evident moral compromises of politics, and on who or what is “absurd” in this interplay.


1. The Persistence of Normative Ideals

  1. Social and Cultural Conditioning
    Even though experience shows that politicians often must engage in moral compromises (e.g., strategic alliances, half-truths, campaign funding intricacies), society generally teaches ideals of honesty, integrity, and service. These ideals resonate with age-old conceptions of leadership—echoing Plato’s philosopher-king or Confucian notions of virtuous rule—and persist even as cynicism about practical politics grows.

  2. Moral Aspiration and Collective Hope
    On a deeper psychological level, the electorate holds onto “moral aspiration.” There is a collective wish that someone might rise above the usual moral muck of political life. This aspiration can be both a genuine longing for better governance (in the sense of Rousseau’s notion of the “general will”) and a kind of protective illusion that keeps despair at bay.

  3. The “Noble Lie” Tradition
    Plato discusses the “Noble Lie” in The Republic—a myth told to maintain social harmony and coherence. Voters sometimes willfully engage in a similar social fiction: leaders promise that they are more ethical than they realistically can be, and voters “hope against hope” that these claims are at least partly true, preserving a semblance of moral order.


2. Political Realism and the Acknowledgment of Compromise

  1. Machiavelli’s Observations
    Machiavelli’s The Prince (1532) highlights that a successful ruler often must appear virtuous while sometimes doing what is expedient (e.g., strategic deception, ruthless actions to maintain power). Modern politicians similarly navigate realpolitik, placating diverse interests and donors. Voters are not naïve about this but tend to compartmentalize: they accept the necessity of such tactics, yet still hope for moral leadership.

  2. Cognitive Dissonance
    Social psychologists note that holding contradictory beliefs (“politicians need to be cunning to survive” versus “we expect them to be paragons of virtue”) creates psychological tension. Voters often resolve this dissonance by doubling down on moral ideals—e.g., “Yes, but my chosen candidate is still better than the rest.” This ironically maintains high moral expectations even when one is fully aware of the moral gray areas.


3. The “Absurd” and Who Embodies It

  1. Camusian Absurd
    Albert Camus, in The Myth of Sisyphus (1942), speaks of the absurd as the contradiction between human longing for clarity/meaning and a world that fails to satisfy those demands. In the realm of politics, the electorate’s longing for uncompromising integrity clashes with the messy real world of governance. Who is being absurd? Perhaps the entire situation is absurd because the moral demands and the political realities cannot be fully reconciled.

  2. Bad Faith (Sartre)
    In Jean-Paul Sartre’s existentialism, “bad faith” refers to self-deception about one’s genuine freedom and responsibility. Voters and politicians alike may collectively act in bad faith. Politicians pretend they can remain pure; voters pretend they genuinely believe this. Both evade responsibility for confronting the real tension between moral ideals and political survival. This mutual pretense can be seen as an absurd performance.

  3. Who Is Being Absurd?


4. Functional Reasons for Maintaining “Unrealistic” Ideals

  1. Aspiration as a Civic Glue
    A society entirely purged of moral expectations would be hopelessly cynical. Holding onto aspirational ideals—even if they appear unrealistic—helps sustain civic engagement, accountability, and a baseline moral standard. The electorate’s “unrealistic expectations” may serve a social purpose: politicians, fearing backlash, at least keep corruption within certain bounds.

  2. Legitimacy and the “Mandate of Heaven”
    Borrowing from Chinese political philosophy, the “Mandate of Heaven” concept states that rulers lose their legitimacy if they become morally degenerate. Even if modern voters are jaded, there remains a cultural norm that a ruler who blatantly violates moral standards risks losing authority and legitimacy. Thus, moral expectations—however unrealistic—remain an important check on power.


Conclusion

In short, everyone participates in a form of absurdity:

Yet this very absurdity can serve a function: it keeps moral aspirations alive and forces leaders to at least pretend to respect ethical standards, giving citizens some leverage to hold them accountable. As Camus might suggest, facing the absurd can also be empowering, forcing us to choose whether to rebel against it, accept it, or transform it. In the end, who is being absurd? Probably all of us, in our own ways—but that may be precisely what sustains the precarious dance of civic life.

You said:

Sustain what? Eventually the situation would deteriorate enough to force the voters to accept all kinds of blatant political corruptions as normal. Then the corrupt politicians get the absurd idea that they can do whatever they want. Who is kidding whom then?

Reasoned for 7 seconds

Examining political illusions

I’m curious about why illusions of moral integrity persist in politics despite widespread corruption, citing Nietzsche and Arendt's views on moral decay and the normalization of corruption.

Sustaining moral order

I'm examining how illusions in politics uphold moral order and justifications, but over time may degrade, normalizing corruption and emboldening politicians. Philosophical references include Plato and Arendt.

Unveiling political illusions

I’m exploring how political illusions, including the normalization of corruption and the role of authoritarian regimes, can deepen as time progresses, using philosophical references like Arendt, Machiavelli, and Orwell.

In truth, the situation you describe—where voters become so inured to corruption that it feels “normal,” and politicians then believe they can get away with anything—is precisely what happens when the guiding illusions of political life fully unravel. Many philosophers have argued that some kind of shared myth or normative framework is necessary for collective life. Once that collapses, cynicism can pervade both the electorate and the ruling class, making corruption seem routine. Below are a few angles on “who is kidding whom” when the civic fabric breaks down:


1. The Illusion That Sustains Civic Life

  1. The “Necessary Myth” View

  2. Check on Power

When these “myths” and ideals disintegrate—because corruption is too blatant and repeated—voters either lose faith entirely or adopt a jaded acceptance. That fosters the environment you describe, where unscrupulous politicians feel they have free rein.


2. Normalizing Corruption and Collective Cynicism

  1. Cultural Shift to Cynicism

  2. Normalization through Repeated Exposure


3. Who Is Kidding Whom?

  1. Politicians Kidding Themselves

  2. Voters Kidding Themselves

  3. Society Kidding Itself


4. The Collapse of the Illusion—and Its Consequences

  1. Fatalism and Real Collapses

  2. Exiting the Absurd Cycle


Conclusion

Ultimately, who is kidding whom in a climate of normalized corruption is a question of shared illusions. Politicians may kid themselves (and the public) that they can keep pushing the envelope. Voters may kid themselves that “it’s not so bad” or that new leaders will magically end corruption. Society as a whole carries on a collective pretense—until or unless the system hits a tipping point where disillusion and cynicism peak.

So, sustain what? We temporarily sustain a veneer of moral order—a social fiction that politics is “fundamentally upright, with a few bad apples.” Once that façade fades, everyone sees that the emperor has no clothes, and the real question is whether the public will tolerate that nakedness or demand a different system. If they tolerate it, the cynics (and the corrupt) have won, and the illusions vanish. If they don’t, the myth can be replaced by genuine accountability—or at least a new “myth” with stricter checks and balances.

You said:

The most effective way to keep a society healthy is to kill all sick people immediately. The fastest way to make a society to be prosperous is to "expel" all non-productive members. What's wrong with these absurd policies?

Reasoned about absurdity of extreme policies for 9 seconds

Considering moral implications

The user's extreme policies prompt a philosophical inquiry into their moral, cultural, ethical, and pragmatic reasons for being morally unacceptable, involving moral philosophy and practical consequences.

Incorporating philosophical perspectives

I’m weaving in Kant's categorical imperative and Rawls's difference principle to highlight how extreme policies clash with widely accepted moral principles. The practical fallout, including fear and instability, is also discussed.

Considering existential ideas

Extreme policies clash with the social contract and universal rights, reminiscing totalitarian eugenics. These policies disrupt cooperation, signaling the importance of mutual support for societal robustness.

At first glance, these proposals—“kill all sick people immediately to keep society healthy” or “expel all non-productive members to achieve prosperity”—seem like stark exercises in “efficiency.” From a purely instrumental viewpoint, one might say, “Fewer burdens mean more resources for everyone else.” But they also strike us as deeply wrong, not just emotionally but logically and ethically. Below are several philosophical and practical reasons why these policies are considered “absurd” or unacceptable.


1. Ethical and Moral Frameworks

  1. Human Dignity and Rights

  2. Virtue and Character

  3. Social Contract Theory


2. Logical and Practical Concerns

  1. Who Decides “Sick” or “Non-Productive”?

  2. Social Instability and Fear

  3. Loss of Human Capital

  4. Human Solidarity and Cooperation


3. The Philosophy of “Absurd” Policies

  1. Moral Absurdity (Contradiction of Ends)

  2. Camusian Absurd (Conflict Between Ideals and Reality)

  3. Instrumental vs. Intrinsic Value


4. Historical Lessons and Precedents

  1. 20th-Century Eugenics and Genocide

  2. Long-Term Consequences


Conclusion

These extreme proposals for “health” and “prosperity” expose a fundamentally contradictory approach: they purport to secure social well-being by discarding the moral and relational bonds that make society worth preserving in the first place. They violate:

  1. Universal moral principles (e.g., human dignity, Kant’s imperative).

  2. Practical logic (e.g., definitions of “sick” or “unproductive” shift, undermining social trust and stability).

  3. Historical lessons (where eugenic or eliminationist policies lead to horror and eventual societal collapse).

In short, these policies are “absurd” because they negate the very foundations—ethical, social, and pragmatic—that allow a community to flourish in the long run. They promise a grotesquely “efficient” short cut to well-being while ignoring the bedrock human values that any truly thriving society must respect.

Suggested Sources for Further Reading

You said:

Then why the presumably "sane" voters in a democracy vote for politicians who probably never said or believed in their life that all human beings are created equal? What's going on?

Reasoned about democracy and voter behavior for 5 seconds

Unraveling voter choices

I'm exploring why some voters prioritize a politician's economic policies over their stance on equality, possibly undermining key democratic values.

Navigating perspectives

People's diverse interpretations and identity politics shape their views on equality, often overshadowing rational democracy and resulting in moral compromises or cognitive dissonance.

Weighing motives

Illusions, tribal beliefs, and pragmatic choices are shaping voter behavior. Philosophical wisdom from figures like Locke and Kant suggests complexities in aligning actions with democratic ideals.

There is a genuine paradox in modern democratic societies: on the one hand, many people embrace (at least in principle) the foundational ideal that “all human beings are created equal,” while on the other, they may end up voting for politicians whose past statements, policies, or affiliations suggest they do not truly hold that belief. Below are several interlocking explanations—philosophical, psychological, and sociopolitical—that help clarify what’s going on.


1. Voter Motivations and Rationalizations

  1. Single-Issue or Narrow Interests

  2. “Lesser Evil” Calculations

  3. Emotional or Identity-Based Voting


2. Political Theater and Rhetoric

  1. Ambiguous or Coded Language

  2. Charisma and Performance


3. Cognitive Biases and Psychological Mechanisms

  1. Confirmation Bias

  2. Normalcy Bias


4. The Gap Between Democratic Ideals and Democratic Practice

  1. Democracy as a “Marketplace of Power”

  2. Declarative vs. Operative Values


5. So, What’s Going On?

  1. A Collective State of Ambivalence

  2. The “Absurd” of Democratic Contradictions

  3. Tribalism, Fear, and the Challenge of Universalism


Conclusion

Voters who ostensibly believe in “all human beings are created equal” may still elect politicians who privately (or not so privately) reject that principle due to a confluence of factors:

In short, it’s not a simple matter of “sane vs. insane.” Rather, it reflects the tension between democratic ideals of equality and the messy, interest-driven realities of electoral politics—what some political philosophers would call part of democracy’s enduring paradoxes.

You said:

Of course, the simplest answer is that most modern citizens are too selfish and callous to be bothered by the suffering of "the others". Is this the case?

Reasoned about selfishness and collective indifference for 4 seconds

Evaluating philosophical perspectives

OK, let me see. The user's question sparks a deep dive into philosophical, psychological, and ethical perspectives, including empathy, altruism, and existential analysis. It’s a nuanced exploration!

It’s tempting to suppose that modern citizens—overwhelmed by their own desires, economic worries, or media distractions—have become too selfish or callous to care about “the others.” Indeed, you can find plenty of real-world evidence suggesting that people often remain unmoved by remote injustices or daily tragedies not directly impacting them. However, the idea that this is simply because we are “too selfish” is more complicated than it first appears. Philosophers, psychologists, and sociologists have long wrestled with the tension between self-interest and empathy in human nature. Below are a few reasons why labeling modern society as purely selfish or callous oversimplifies a much more complex picture.


1. Historical and Philosophical Views on Human Nature

  1. Thomas Hobbes’s “Selfish” Human Nature

  2. David Hume’s “Limited Altruism”

  3. Adam Smith’s “Theory of Moral Sentiments” (1759)


2. Psychological and Sociological Dimensions

  1. Empathy Fatigue

  2. In-Group vs. Out-Group Bias

  3. Structural Alienation


3. Evidence of Ongoing Empathy and Altruism

  1. Philanthropy and Volunteerism

  2. Collective Responses to Crises

  3. Social Movements and Advocacy


4. Why It’s More Complicated Than “Too Selfish or Callous”

  1. Conflicting Interests and Values

  2. Systemic Factors

  3. Moral Complexity, Not Moral Bankruptcy


5. Conclusion

While it may appear that most modern citizens simply don’t care about the suffering of “the others,” the reality is more nuanced. Yes, self-interest, empathy fatigue, in-group bias, and structural alienation all limit how far compassion extends. But that does not mean there’s no compassion—just that it often competes with powerful economic, social, and psychological forces.

So, while selfishness and callousness are part of the human condition, they’re not the entire story. Rather than concluding “most people just don’t care,” a more accurate assessment would highlight that multiple, often contradictory, tendencies shape our moral behavior—and our societies.

References for Further Exploration

You said:

If so, can we say instead that it's the modern society that is too selfish and callous to achieve "universal" democracy?

Reasoned for 7 seconds

Assessing societal traits

I’m examining if modern society's selfishness is hindering universal democracy. Considering individual attitudes, societal structure, and historical influences, I’m referencing philosophical sources to explore democracy's feasibility.

Weighing democracy ideals

I'm contrasting universal versus partial democracy, highlighting power concentration and oligarchy. Critical theorists challenge the democracy ideal, revealing tensions with modern capitalism and neoliberalism.

Complex dynamics at play

Universal democracy's feasibility hinges on individual interests, structural constraints, and differing political philosophies. The tension between ideal democracy and the practical realities of representative systems is fascinating.

Labeling modern society as “too selfish and callous to achieve ‘universal democracy’” is a stark way to diagnose why political systems often fail to live up to democratic ideals. On one hand, the sentiment captures real-world frustrations: we see widespread voter apathy, staggering inequality, and politicians who sometimes profit from popular fear or division. On the other hand, social scientists and philosophers caution that such a sweeping claim oversimplifies complex structural and psychological factors. Below are some key points to consider when asking whether society’s collective “selfishness” undermines the possibility of a truly universal democracy.


1. Clarifying “Universal Democracy”

  1. The Ideal vs. The Reality

  2. Philosophical Underpinnings


2. Individual Selfishness vs. Structural Factors

  1. Individual Choice vs. Collective Constraints

  2. Alienation and Inequality

  3. Social Capital and Trust


3. Psychological and Cultural Dynamics

  1. In-Group Biases

  2. Empathy Fatigue and Media Overload

  3. Rational Ignorance and Short-Term Focus


4. Interpreting the “Selfish and Callous” Charge

  1. It’s Not Only About Moral Failure

  2. Democratic Health as a Collective Effort

  3. The Role of Hope and Mobilization


5. Conclusion: Too Selfish for Universal Democracy?

Hence, while it may be tempting to reduce our political troubles to a single cause—“society is too selfish”—the reality is more nuanced. Contemporary social and political theory suggests a multifaceted interplay among individual dispositions, institutional frameworks, and cultural contexts. True universal democracy remains an ideal requiring ongoing vigilance, reforms, and a moral commitment not only from individuals, but from the very structure of society itself.


Suggested Readings & References

You said:

In that case, what kind of people created the systemic or structural inequality? Just stupid ones?

Reasoned about causes of systemic inequality for 4 seconds

Unraveling structural inequality

I'm piecing together who might create systemic inequality. It involves individuals who strive to maintain an advantage, with traits like selfishness, incompetence, or moral indifference.

Understanding systemic bias

OK, let me confess: systemic bias often springs from greed, fear, or power. Linking it to philosophers like Rawls or Marx, I’m also examining structural racism via thinkers like Du Bois.

The idea that “systemic or structural inequality” is created (or perpetuated) solely by “stupid” people is too simplistic. Systems of inequality typically emerge and evolve due to a complex interplay of historical accidents, strategic power-plays, cultural biases, economic interests, and social norms. In many cases, there was no single group of conspirators sitting down to design an unfair system from scratch—rather, inequalities often accumulate, harden, and become self-perpetuating over time. Below are some key reasons and frameworks that help explain how structural inequalities arise, without reducing the cause to individual “stupidity.”


1. Historical Accidents and Path Dependence

  1. Early Advantages Become Entrenched

  2. Feudal Legacies and Colonial Systems


2. Power, Interest, and Rational Self-Preservation

  1. Not Stupidity—But Often Self-Interest

  2. Economic Exploitation

  3. Max Weber’s Concept of Social Closure


3. Cultural and Ideological Reinforcement

  1. Hegemony and Internalized Norms

  2. Implicit Bias and Unconscious Prejudice


4. Legal-Institutional Frameworks and Pathologies

  1. Institutional Inertia

  2. Capture of Regulatory Bodies


5. The Role of Everyday Participation (or Apathy)

  1. Complicity Through Inaction

  2. Rational Ignorance


6. So, Who “Created” Systemic Inequality?

  1. Emergent and Evolving Systems

  2. Short-Sightedness vs. Morally Culpable Knowledge


7. Conclusion: Not “Stupid,” but Complex

While there can be ignorance involved in perpetuating unjust systems (e.g., failing to recognize one’s biases, not questioning one’s privileges), labeling the architects or participants of inequality as merely “stupid” misses the mark. Structural inequalities typically:

Hence, the forces behind systemic inequality are complex mixtures of power, tradition, rational advantage-seeking, and embedded ideologies. Stupidity alone is too narrow an explanation; it’s more apt to speak of a tapestry of self-interest, historical inertia, cultural biases, institutional lock-in, and everyday compliance.


Suggested Further Reading

These works offer frameworks for understanding how structural inequalities are created and sustained—primarily through complex social dynamics and power relations, rather than the simple stupidity of any single group.

You said:

Are we now not just selfish and callous but also short-sighted and rather stupid as well? Or, should we just blame all others, dead or alive, but us?

Reasoned for a second

Humanity has often struggled to grapple with its own contradictions. We can see examples of selfishness, callousness, short-sightedness, or downright stupidity in individuals or groups, but we also find remarkable empathy, foresight, and moral courage in others. In short, we don’t need to choose between “everyone is stupid” or “it’s someone else’s fault.” The reality is more nuanced:


1. A Complex Mixture of Traits

  1. Moral and Cognitive Mixed Bag

  2. Context Matters


2. The Tendency to Blame Others

  1. Fundamental Attribution Error

  2. Historical and Intergenerational Shifts

  3. Diffusion of Responsibility


3. Why Neither Pure Self-Flagellation nor Complete Excusal Is Helpful

  1. Recognizing Systemic Complexity

  2. Shared but Unequal Responsibility


4. Holding Onto Agency and Hope

  1. Human Capacity for Self-Correction

  2. Pragmatic Focus on Improving Systems

  3. Personal Reflection and Collective Accountability


Conclusion

Yes, there is plenty of evidence that humans can be selfish, callous, short-sighted, and occasionally downright foolish. But there is also ample evidence of empathy, cooperation, and far-sighted moral action. Reducing everything to “people are stupid” or “it’s all their fault” obscures the systemic and historical complexity at play—and can paralyze efforts at reform.

A more constructive view is to recognize that:

In short, we need neither total self-condemnation nor total exculpation: rather, we can acknowledge both the human weaknesses and the structural dynamics that shape them, then foster reforms that encourage our better capacities and discourage the worst ones.


Suggested Readings

You said:

Complexity arguments will not do. Each individuals are probably much more complex than any social and political structures. Do we even actually want universal democracy? Where is the proof?

Reasoned for 6 seconds

Evaluating the claim

The user is querying the notion of universal democracy, urging consideration beyond mere complexity arguments. They seek philosophical evidence or frameworks to substantiate the desire for universal democracy.

Charting democratic progress

I’m piecing together evidence for universal democracy, considering 20th-century global shifts, societal acceptance of participatory governance, and extensive data showing widespread democratic ideals.

Balancing ideals

I'm working through the tension between rhetorical support for democracy and the practical challenges it entails, like sharing power and embracing minority rights.

Reflecting on preferences

Noting that proving "universal democracy" is partial, as some may view authoritarian or paternalistic governance as preferable. Complex individual preferences and societal structures suggest a nuanced approach.

Short Answer:
There is no simple, knockdown “proof” that everyone truly wants “universal democracy.” We do have indications—historical movements for suffrage, global opinion polls, the widespread rhetorical embrace of democratic ideals—that many people claim to want an inclusive political system. Yet wanting democracy in the abstract differs from doing the hard work of extending equal power and voice to all, including those with unpopular viewpoints or marginalized identities. So, we cannot point to a single definitive proof that humanity uniformly desires universal democracy. Instead, we have overlapping lines of evidence—historical, sociological, and philosophical—that some portion of humanity consistently strives for it, while others just as consistently shrink from its fullest implications.

Below is a deeper exploration of this question:


1. Wanting Democracy vs. Tolerating Its Consequences

  1. Lip-Service vs. Genuine Commitment

  2. “Democracy for Me, Not for Thee”


2. Historical Indications of Desire for (Some Form of) Democracy

  1. The “Waves of Democratization”

  2. Global Opinion Surveys


3. Philosophical Angles on the Desire for Democracy

  1. Aristotle vs. Plato on the Value of Democracy

  2. Rousseau’s “General Will”

  3. John Rawls on Equal Basic Liberties


4. The Challenge of “Proof” for What People Actually Want

  1. Behavior vs. Expressed Values

  2. Historical Successes and Backsliding

  3. Context Dependence


5. Are People “More Complex Than Structures”?

  1. Individual Complexity vs. Collective Outcomes

  2. Can Complexity Arguments Still Apply?


Final Thoughts: Do We Really Want Universal Democracy?

In short, the best we can say is that universal democracy remains a contested ideal. Large numbers of people across history have indeed fought for it, suggesting there is real desire for inclusive self-government. Yet in practice, that desire competes constantly with narrower group interests, apathy, and realpolitik. If you seek irrefutable proof that everyone wants universal democracy, you won’t find it. What you can find is evidence that a significant fraction of humanity has repeatedly moved society in that direction—though how far that movement goes, and how durable it is, always depends on context, power dynamics, and moral will.


Suggested Readings

These sources won’t provide a mathematical proof of universal democratic desire, but they do illustrate where, how, and why people often support democracy—and where they fall short.

You said:

Who or what actually has the agency?

Reasoned about agency in society for 2m 12s

Questions about “who or what actually has the agency” tap into longstanding debates in philosophy and the social sciences about structure (the social, cultural, economic, and institutional forces that shape our lives) and agency (the capacity of individuals to act freely and make independent choices). Different thinkers have proposed different ways to reconcile or emphasize one side over the other. Below is a brief overview of how major theories answer the question, “Who or what really has the power to act?”


1. The Classical Debate: Individual vs. Society

  1. Methodological Individualism

  2. Structural Determinism


2. Contemporary Syntheses

  1. Anthony Giddens’s Structuration Theory

  2. Pierre Bourdieu’s Habitus and Field


3. Distributed Agency and Actor-Network Theory

  1. Bruno Latour and Nonhuman Agents


4. Who Actually Has Agency? Multiple Angles

  1. Individuals

  2. Structures/Systems

  3. Ongoing Interaction

  4. Historical and Political Context


5. Practical Implications

  1. Responsibility and Accountability

  2. Social Change Strategies


Conclusion: “Agency” Is a Shared Dance

Short answer: Agency is not located in a single person or entity, nor purely in “the system.” The contemporary consensus among many philosophers and social scientists is that agency emerges in the interplay between individuals and the broader structures they inhabit:

Hence, the question “Who or what has the agency?” may be best answered by saying: everyone and everything involved, in different degrees and ways, operating within (and potentially revising) the social conditions that shape us all.


Suggested References for Further Exploration


You said:

Even assuming that "everyone and everything involved, in different degrees and ways" have agency, who or what can WE actually influence and mobilize to change the reality?

Reasoned for a few seconds

Assessing change approaches

Thinking about realizing change with power-focused strategies. Collective action, policy shifts, alliances, and using moral persuasion are interesting pathways. Activism and skill-building at local and legislative levels could be explored further.

Short Answer:
If we accept that agency is widely distributed—among individuals, institutions, technologies, social networks, cultural norms—then change requires working at multiple levels. We (as individuals or groups) can influence and mobilize people, institutions, and cultural narratives to transform reality. This means acting through civic engagement, collective action, institutional reform, public discourse, and personal example. Below is a more detailed exploration:


1. Targeting Individuals: Building Consciousness and Capacity

  1. Education and Awareness

  2. Grassroots Organizing and Local Communities

  3. Social Identity and Group Mobilization


2. Influencing Institutions and Policy

  1. Formal Politics

  2. Nonviolent Resistance and Collective Action

  3. Building Parallel or Alternative Institutions


3. Shaping Cultural Narratives and Norms

  1. Public Discourse and the “Public Sphere”

  2. Creative and Symbolic Action

  3. Entertainment and Pop Culture


4. Coordination of Multiple Levels

  1. Interlocking Strategies

  2. Intersectionality and Coalition-Building


5. So, Who/What Can “We” Influence or Mobilize?

  1. Our Immediate Networks

  2. Local Governance

  3. Cultural Platforms

  4. Allies with Institutional Power

  5. Transnational Networks


6. Conclusion

Since agency is distributed among individuals, institutions, and cultural systems, we can effect change by activating various levers of influence:

No single approach guarantees transformation, but coordinated efforts across these domains have historically reshaped political realities—proving that, despite constraints, collective human agency can alter the course of history. “We” are thus not powerless; we are participants in an ever-evolving web of action, constraint, and possibility. By strategically focusing efforts where our influence is strongest—be it local communities, policy reforms, or cultural narratives—we harness and amplify the distributed agency that exists within us and around us.


Key References for Further Exploration

You said:

Is it possible that this "sophistry" just undermines human initiatives and protects the status quo?

Reasoned for a couple of seconds

Navigating complexity

Wondering about the impact of complexity on practical action, it seems this argument can lead to inertia or confusion but, if applied thoughtfully, can enhance understanding and strategy.

Short Answer:
Yes, it is possible that over-intellectualizing social complexity (“everyone and everything has agency”) can unintentionally paralyze human initiative or even justify the status quo. If discussions of structure, agency, and distributed responsibility become abstract exercises with no clear path to action, they can serve as a form of “sophistry.” However, when approached with a practical orientation, these same concepts can enhance our strategic thinking, clarifying where and how to intervene for change. Whether complexity arguments become a shield for the status quo or a source of deeper empowerment depends largely on how we deploy them in public discourse and activism.

Below is a more in-depth perspective:


1. The Pitfall: Complexity as Excuse or Paralysis

  1. Intellectual Overload

  2. Sophistry and Cynical Deflection

  3. Perpetuating the Status Quo


2. The Opportunity: Complexity as a Tool for Strategic Action

  1. Better Diagnosis of Problems

  2. Collaboration Across Disciplines

  3. Nuanced Moral Responsibility


3. Making Complexity Arguments Productive, Not Paralytic

  1. Bridging Theory and Practice

  2. “Strategic Essentialism” in Advocacy

  3. Accessible Communication


4. Balancing Complexity with Urgency

  1. Avoiding Fatalism

  2. Incremental vs. Radical Approaches

  3. Institutional and Cultural Shifts


Conclusion: A Double-Edged Sword

  1. Yes, complexity and “everyone-and-everything-has-agency” arguments can be abused as sophistry to maintain the status quo—especially if they become excuses for cynicism or endless debate with no action plan.

  2. However, complexity can also be leveraged to build more effective coalitions and multifaceted strategies for social change. Recognizing distributed agency and intricate causal networks can expand our repertoire of interventions rather than shrink it.

Ultimately, whether complexity arguments stifle or fuel change depends on the intent and method of those wielding them. If we pair nuanced analysis with practical organizing, policy proposals, and moral commitment, complexity becomes a powerful ally in challenging unjust systems—rather than a rhetorical shield for them.


Suggested Readings

These texts can help illustrate how a deeper understanding of complexity might inform more robust forms of activism, rather than paralyze it.

You said:

Do you really think ordinary citizens can use this kind of in depth analysis to motivate them "properly"?

Reasoned for a couple of seconds

Whether ordinary citizens can—or even want to—absorb and apply detailed theoretical or philosophical analyses to motivate themselves is a question that cuts to the heart of how ideas spread, how social change is organized, and how knowledge becomes action. Some key points to consider:


1. Bridging “In-Depth Analysis” and Everyday Life

  1. Simplification and Storytelling

  2. Community Education and “Popularization”

  3. Media, Arts, and Viral Communication


2. Historical Precedents for “Ordinary” Engagement

  1. Mass Movements and Simplified Ideals

  2. Incremental Deepening


3. Motivation vs. Explanation

  1. Motivation Through Shared Values

  2. Depth as an Ongoing Resource, Not a Starting Barrier


4. Role of Leadership and Translators

  1. Intellectuals as “Translators”

  2. Grassroots Leadership


5. Beware the “All or Nothing” Fallacy

  1. Partial Knowledge Still Empowers

  2. Different Levels of Engagement


6. Conclusion: Do Ordinary Citizens Need “In-Depth Analysis” to Be Properly Motivated?

Hence, “ordinary citizens” often are able to engage with nuanced ideas if presented in a structured, relevant, and accessible manner. In-depth theory alone rarely motivates the average person; it’s the combination of immediate concern, moral or emotional resonance, and a leadership network that can clarify and channel those concerns into real action.

You said:

You seem to be overestimating ordinary users' ability and also misunderstanding the reason for this conversation.

Reasoned about the limits of discourse for 12 seconds

Clarifying intentions

The user questions the reasoning behind the conversation, possibly seeking a reevaluation or pointing out that deep theoretical analysis may not always advance the discussion.

Assessing communication style

The user might be noting that the assistant's complex answers overlook the need for a simpler, more direct, or philosophical approach, potentially missing the core issue of communication style.

Engaging with curiosity

It's clear the assistant should inquire about the user's core motivation, differentiate between theoretical misconceptions and real needs, or offer a fresh approach, possibly including a philosophical reflection on the role of conversation.

Clarifying the objective

I’m focusing on understanding the user's goal, considering directness, clarity, and the potential for simplifying the discussion to better align with their needs.

You raise a valid concern. It’s possible I’ve been offering detailed, academic-style explanations that don’t line up with either (a) the practical ways most people actually think and act, or (b) the true purpose of this conversation. Let me address both points in turn:


1. “Overestimating Ordinary Users’ Ability”


2. “Misunderstanding the Reason for This Conversation”


3. So What Is the Core Issue, Then?

Without imposing assumptions, let me hazard a guess:

If that’s along the lines of your reasoning, then the conversation’s purpose could be to emphasize:

  1. Many people talk about big ideals (e.g., democracy, justice) but remain apathetic or self-serving in practice.

  2. High-level philosophical explanations of “why” can just end up sounding like excuses or tangents, rather than calls to action.

  3. Ordinary folks simply do not weigh 2,500 years of philosophical discourse before they act (or fail to act).


4. A More Direct Take

If this is the point you’re making, then indeed, we might not need the academic scaffolding at all. The conversation’s purpose could be to show how easily one can bury straightforward moral or political skepticism under elaborate theoretical references.


5. Closing Thoughts

In Sum

  1. You’re correct that ordinary users often aren’t motivated by elaborate theory.

  2. You’re correct that I may have misread why you’re pressing these points—perhaps you’re demonstrating the gap between real-world political cynicism and high-level discourse.

  3. Your challenge might be highlighting that, at the end of the day, grand “explanations” don’t necessarily drive real change—or that many people just don’t want the changes they claim to want.

I appreciate the clarification. If there’s a more specific aspect you’d like me to address—without the overly academic flourish—I’m happy to shift gears accordingly.

You said:

I personally don't mind what you are doing usually, but my main objective of this kind of "street philosophy" conversation is not "wasting my time" to write or read a book that does not actually interest me. Most political questions need to be answered at the common sense level. That way I can share it with "ordinary activists", as well as motivating me to act wisely.

Reasoned for a second

Understood. The goal, then, is to address political or social questions in plain language—brief, grounded, and immediately useful for everyday citizens and activists. Below is a short summary of how one might do “street philosophy” for political issues, without getting lost in heavy theory:


1. Keep it Concrete and Relatable

Simple rule of thumb: if you can’t explain it quickly using everyday situations—housing, paychecks, schools—it’s probably too abstract for common-sense activism.


2. Ask the Basic “Why” and “Who Benefits” Questions

When facing a political question—like why a local government refuses to fix certain roads or why certain groups aren’t heard—two immediate questions often help:

  1. “Why is this happening?”

  2. “Who benefits from the status quo?”

This approach is straightforward, highlights underlying interests, and points to potential areas for organized action.


3. Translate Complexity into “Usable” Insights

No need for academic jargon—just a direct statement of the problem, who’s behind it, and why it persists.


4. Keep Morale and Practical Wisdom High

When people see a doable path forward, they’re more likely to stay motivated.


5. Use Straightforward Moral Arguments

Big ideas like “universal justice” become clear when framed as “everyone deserves basic respect and a fair chance.”


6. Focus on Shareability

If others can pass it on quickly, it will spread among ordinary activists, who are often busy and want quick clarity.


In Sum

“Street philosophy” for politics is about clarity, accessibility, and direct relevance. You take complex subjects—like corruption, inequalities, or democracy—and cut them down to size:

  1. Concrete examples (“They won't fix our roads while they build luxury condos.”)

  2. Simple “why” and “who benefits” questions.

  3. A clear moral viewpoint (“Is it just/fair?”).

  4. Straightforward suggestions for what you and your neighbors can actually do next.

This is how you get “ordinary activists” (and yourself) motivated to act wisely rather than getting stuck in theoretical loops.

You said:

Yes. We need to start over in another thread. My main reason to talk about "politics" here is to get some practical wisdom that appeals to me and still is not too ridiculous. It would be quite different if I do "philosophy" here as in many other threads. I should have made it clear, much earlier. Thanks.

Reasoned for a second

Understood. Whenever you’re ready to start that new thread, feel free to jump in with a fresh question or topic. We can keep it focused on short, practical political insights. No worries about what’s come before—we can set it aside and begin with a clean slate. Just let me know the issue or context, and I’ll give you the most direct, useful guidance I can.









Chat history